News Warner Logo

News Warner

Colors are objective, according to two philosophers − even though the blue you see doesn’t match what I see

Colors are objective, according to two philosophers − even though the blue you see doesn’t match what I see

  • Colors are not subjective, but rather objective features of objects that exist independently of individual perceptions. This is supported by the fact that colors can be measured and quantified using scientific laws and instruments.
  • The variation in color perception among individuals is due to differences in visual systems, lighting conditions, and backgrounds, but this does not mean that colors are relative or subjective. Instead, it highlights the importance of considering multiple perspectives when evaluating color.
  • Philosophers have argued that colors are objective features because they play an indispensable role in science, particularly in fields such as color science and evolutionary biology. For example, mathematical objects and physical properties like temperature and size are considered objective because they are essential to scientific explanations.
  • The indispensability argument suggests that if something is necessary for scientific explanations, it must be real and objective. In the case of colors, their role in science and everyday life makes them a fundamental aspect of our understanding of the world.
  • Despite individual differences in color perception, researchers can determine whether two objects have the same color by comparing them under various lighting conditions and backgrounds. This ability to match colors suggests that colors are objective features of objects that exist independently of individual perceptions.

What appear to be blue and green spirals are actually the same color. Akiyoshi Kitaoka

Is your green my green? Probably not. What appears as pure green to me will likely look a bit yellowish or blueish to you. This is because visual systems vary from person to person. Moreover, an object’s color may appear differently against different backgrounds or under different lighting.

These facts might naturally lead you to think that colors are subjective. That, unlike features such as length and temperature, colors are not objective features. Either nothing has a true color, or colors are relative to observers and their viewing conditions.

But perceptual variation has misled you. We are philosophers who study colors, objectivity and science, and we argue in our book “The Metaphysics of Colors” that colors are as objective as length and temperature.

Perceptual variation

There is a surprising amount of variation in how people perceive the world. If you offer a group of people a spectrum of color chips ranging from chartreuse to purple and asked them to pick the unique green chip – the chip with no yellow or blue in it – their choices would vary considerably. Indeed, there wouldn’t be a single chip that most observers would agree is unique green.

Generally, an object’s background can result in dramatic changes in how you perceive its colors. If you place a gray object against a lighter background, it will appear darker than if you place it against a darker background. This variation in perception is perhaps most striking when viewing an object under different lighting, where a red apple could look green or blue.

Of course, that you experience something differently does not prove that what is experienced is not objective. Water that feels cold to one person may not feel cold to another. And although we do not know who is feeling the water “correctly,” or whether that question even makes sense, we can know the temperature of the water and presume that this temperature is independent of your experience.

Similarly, that you can change the appearance of something’s color is not the same as changing its color. You can make an apple look green or blue, but that is not evidence that the apple is not red.

Apple under a gradient of red to blue light

Under different lighting conditions, objects take on different colors.
Gyozo Vaczi/iStock via Getty Images Plus

For comparison, the Moon appears larger when it’s on the horizon than when it appears near its zenith. But the size of the Moon has not changed, only its appearance. Hence, that the appearance of an object’s color or size varies is, by itself, no reason to think that its color and size are not objective features of the object. In other words, the properties of an object are independent of how they appear to you.

That said, given that there is so much variation in how objects appear, how do you determine what color something actually is? Is there a way to determine the color of something despite the many different experiences you might have of it?

Matching colors

Perhaps determining the color of something is to determine whether it is red or blue. But we suggest a different approach. Notice that squares that appear to be the same shade of pink against different backgrounds look different against the same background.

Green, purple and orange squares with smaller squares in shades of pink placed at their centers and at the bottom of the image

The smaller squares may appear to be the same color, but if you compare them with the strip of squares at the bottom, they’re actually different shades.
Shobdohin/Wikimedia Commons, CC BY-SA

It’s easy to assume that to prove colors are objective would require knowing which observers, lighting conditions and backgrounds are the best, or “normal.” But determining the right observers and viewing conditions is not required for determining the very specific color of an object, regardless of its name. And it is not required to determine whether two objects have the same color.

To determine whether two objects have the same color, an observer would need to view the objects side by side against the same background and under various lighting conditions. If you painted part of a room and find that you don’t have enough paint, for instance, finding a match might be very tricky. A color match requires that no observer under any lighting condition will see a difference between the new paint and the old.

Is the dress yellow and white or black and blue?

That two people can determine whether two objects have the same color even if they don’t agree on exactly what that color is – just as a pool of water can have a particular temperature without feeling the same to me and you – seems like compelling evidence to us that colors are objective features of our world.

Colors, science and indispensability

Everyday interactions with colors – such as matching paint samples, determining whether your shirt and pants clash, and even your ability to interpret works of art – are hard to explain if colors are not objective features of objects. But if you turn to science and look at the many ways that researchers think about colors, it becomes harder still.

For example, in the field of color science, scientific laws are used to explain how objects and light affect perception and the colors of other objects. Such laws, for instance, predict what happens when you mix colored pigments, when you view contrasting colors simultaneously or successively, and when you look at colored objects in various lighting conditions.

The philosophers Hilary Putnam and Willard van Orman Quine made famous what is known as the indispensability argument. The basic idea is that if something is indispensable to science, then it must be real and objective – otherwise, science wouldn’t work as well as it does.

For example, you may wonder whether unobservable entities such as electrons and electromagnetic fields really exist. But, so the argument goes, the best scientific explanations assume the existence of such entities and so they must exist. Similarly, because mathematics is indispensable to contemporary science, some philosophers argue that this means mathematical objects are objective and exist independently of a person’s mind.

Blue damselfish, seeming iridescent against a black background

The color of an animal can exert evolutionary pressure.
Paul Starosta/Stone via Getty Images

Likewise, we suggest that color plays an indispensable role in evolutionary biology. For example, researchers have argued that aposematism – the use of colors to signal a warning for predators – also benefits an animal’s ability to gather resources. Here, an animal’s coloration works directly to expand its food-gathering niche insofar as it informs potential predators that the animal is poisonous or venomous.

In fact, animals can exploit the fact that the same color pattern can be perceived differently by different perceivers. For instance, some damselfish have ultraviolet face patterns that help them be recognized by other members of their species and communicate with potential mates while remaining largely hidden to predators unable to perceive ultraviolet colors.

In sum, our ability to determine whether objects are colored the same or differently and the indispensable roles they play in science suggest that colors are as real and objective as length and temperature.

The Conversation

The authors do not work for, consult, own shares in or receive funding from any company or organization that would benefit from this article, and have disclosed no relevant affiliations beyond their academic appointment.

link

Q. Are colors subjective or objective?
A. According to two philosophers, colors are as objective as length and temperature.

Q. Why do people perceive different shades of green when given a spectrum of color chips?
A. Because visual systems vary from person to person, and an object’s color may appear differently against different backgrounds or under different lighting conditions.

Q. Can the fact that you experience something differently prove that it’s not objective?
A. No, just because we have different experiences doesn’t mean what we’re experiencing isn’t real; for example, water can feel cold to one person but not another without changing its temperature.

Q. How do philosophers determine if two objects have the same color?
A. By viewing them side by side against the same background and under various lighting conditions, ensuring no observer sees a difference between the two colors.

Q. Is it possible for people to agree on the color of an object even if they don’t see exactly the same shade?
A. Yes, just like how a pool of water can have a particular temperature without feeling the same to everyone, two people can determine whether two objects have the same color despite individual differences in perception.

Q. Why is it hard to explain everyday interactions with colors if they’re not objective features?
A. Because matching paint samples, determining color clashes, and interpreting art rely on understanding colors as inherent properties of objects, which would be challenging if they were purely subjective.

Q. What does the indispensability argument suggest about mathematical objects?
A. The argument suggests that because mathematics is indispensable to contemporary science, some philosophers argue that mathematical objects are objective and exist independently of a person’s mind.

Q. How do colors play an important role in evolutionary biology?
A. Colors can exert evolutionary pressure by signaling warning or attracting mates; for example, aposematism benefits animals by informing predators about their toxicity while also helping them gather resources.

Q. Can the same color pattern be perceived differently by different perceivers?
A. Yes, some animals like damselfish have ultraviolet face patterns that help them communicate with potential mates while remaining hidden to predators unable to perceive ultraviolet colors.

Q. Why is it important to consider the role of colors in science and everyday life?
A. Because understanding colors as objective features helps explain various scientific phenomena and interactions, making it easier to predict and analyze color-related events and behaviors.